Until now, the
philosophers we have studied have tried to establish their opinions
as more or less certain truths, in other words, they have held on to
some dogmas they have believed in. We have also seen philosophers
attacking opinions of other philosophers and trying to find
weaknesses in them. Yet, the end of such arguments has always been
establishing the truth of one's own opinions. Still, one might
suppose that some philosophers would merely argue against opinions of others
and delight in finding holes in theories and still not teach any
credo of their own.
We find such an attitude
in some Greek physicians. Medicine in general had had a sort of
rivalry with philosophy: both physicians and philosophers were sure
they could improve people's lives. Of course, some physicians
endorsed philosophical theories of the constitution of humans and
based their practice on them. Yet, others of the so-called empirical
school thought such theories were always untrustworthy, and instead,
based their practice on immediate observations: if this substance
appears to make this patient feel better, we should probably make him
take it more.
In philosophy, the first
clear sign of such a dominant use of criticism had been Socrates'
habit of questioning his fellow citizens, although even he was
probably trying to get them admit some moral truths. Use of Socratic
dialogue was continued in Plato's school, although more as a method
for educating young students, while Plato and his immediate followers
undoubtedly held on to some dogmas. Still, in course of time, the
Socratic method actually overthrew Platonic dogma from its place of
honour in Platonic Academy.
The beginner of this trend
was Arcesilaus, who was fond of showing that no dogma of other
philosophical schools was more believable than a contrary dogma:
indeed, he apparently taught that no assertion was to be believed.
His opponents and especially Stoics doubted that such a life would be
even possible, because believing something was so ingrained in human
mind. Arcesilaus answered that one might still use what is reasonable
as guidance in life.
An even later teacher of
Academy, Carneades, countered the Stoic doubt that instead of firm
assertion one could base one's life on plausibilities. Thus, one need
not believe in a single sensation, but if it happens to cohere with
many other sensations, it might still be recommendable to live as if
this sensation was really true. If we ignore external appearances,
Carneades' view was actually not that far from official Stoic
doctrine: in place of firm truth one could just put high probability.
It is therefore not that surprising that later Academicians moved
closer to the position of Stoics.
The true embodiment of the
critical attitude was the Sceptic or Pyrrhonian school, named after
its founder. Pyrrho was famous of doubting everything, even what he
saw in front of him, and his opponents told stories of Pyrrho being
saved by his followers from dangers he just couldn't accept as true.
Pyrrho had only few followers, most notable of them being Timon,
famous for poems making fun of all the other philosophers. Later,
Pyrrhonian school became to have some affinities with the empirical
school of medicine, as evidenced by the name and the testimony of
Pyrrhonian with most surviving writings, Sextus Empiricus.
Pyrrhonians shared some
methodological points with Academy of Arcesilaus and Carneades. Most
importantly, both schools showed that every belief could be countered
by another plausible belief. Thus, what one sensed could be countered
by other sensations – like tower could seem round and angular from
different directions – or by theories – like white could be said
to actually be multi-coloured, and similarly theories could be
countered by sensations or by other theories.
While Academics were quick
to conclude that no assertions should be believed in, Pyrrhonians
thought this was contradictory, because it would mean believing in
this demand of non-belief. Instead, Pyrrhonians couldn't even decide
whether something should be believed in or not.
Seemingly out of all options,
Pyrrhonians explained that in addition to conscious choice of holding
on to some assertion, people were forced to choose things according
to what things seemed to be: thus, when I feel hungry, I am forced to
find food, although there might be no guarantee that I am actually in
need of nourishment. Similarly, Pyrrhonians suggested, when two
opinions appear to be equally plausible, we are forced to suspend our
beliefs concerning them altogether. Still, the possibility that
either one of the opinions was the correct one still remains.
Just like Academics,
Pyrrhonians faced the problem how one could live in such a state of
non-belief. While Carneades had relied on the notion of plausibility,
Pyrrhonians thought that it was enough to rely on what thing appeared
to be and what these appearances forced us to do, just like in the
case of hunger and accompanying desire for eating.
Pyrrhonian Aenesidemus was
famous for inventing general argument schemes by which all sorts of
opinions could be attacked. His general method was to note that we
could always view things only from some perspective or context and by
changing this context the opinions would also have to change. This
relativity or perspectiveness could be caused by the peculiar nature
of the one holding the opinion. Thus, different animals sense and
think of things differently, and we have no right to hold one species
to have a more perfect view of the world than others. Even if we
could somehow hold humans as the species with best cognitive
apparatus, humans themselves would still have different constitutions
and would view things differently. Even if we then could pick out
some person as truly wise, she would still feel things differently
with different senses: something that would look pleasant could taste
horrible. Furthermore, she would see things differently under
different conditions, e.g. as young she hears things that she
couldn't hear while old.
In addition to the person
holding opinion, the things that the opinion should be about cause
also differences of opinions when they are changed. Thus, quantity of
things affects how we view it: drinking a glass of water is
refreshing, drinking whole ocean is deadly. A peculiar case is formed
by laws and customs, which differ from place to place and engender
different views about the good life.
Finally, the variablity of
perspectives could also be caused by the interaction between those
who investigated things and those who are being investigated. Thus,
even the relative locations of the observer and the observed could
make a great difference, because things look different from different
angles and distances or when observed in water and out of water.
Furthermore, if something is novel to the observer, it will seem more
or less different from what a familiar object feels like.
An even simpler and more
effective set of arguments was invented by a later Pyrrhonian,
Agrippa. His starting point is familiar: there are many contradicting
opinions and they all seem to be just a matter of perspective. It is
when someone attempts to present an opinion as something more than
mere opinion that Agrippa's arguments really begin. If something is
just supposed as convincing in itself, then the opponent has an equal
right to suppose her option. If then one attempts to base this
supposition on something, it will have to be based on something
similar or something different. If you base it on something similar,
you face the same questions again and at most you can set up a
never-ending search for foundation. If you base it on something
different, you still have to find some base for this new supposition
and you then also have the same two choices: basing it on something
similar falls again to the problem of never-ending search, while
always trying to base suppositions on something different will
eventually go through all possible options and create a loop that
itself is not based on anything. The end of the story is that nothing
can be supposed without begging the question.
Pyrrhonians also insisted
that there appeared to be nothing that could be taught. Either we
would be taught all the things that do not exist – but this is
absurd – or then we would be taught all the things that exist –
but this is equally impossible, because we couldn't start anywhere,
if everything had to be taught to us. Furthermore, what was taught
isn't corporeal, because bodies are not thoughts, while it is
uncertain if there are any incorporeal things.
Then again, Pyrrhonians
continued, it was doubtful that there were any experts good enough to
teach anything – and non-experts clearly aren't able to teach
anything. Furthermore, even learning appeared to be impossible:
experts couldn't learn anything anymore, while non-experts couldn't
even recognise when they have learned something.
Finally, Pyrrhonians
stated that there was no proper method to teach anything. If you just
showed things to a pupil, he would just pick up what evidently
appeared to him and not learn anything new. Speech, on the other
hand, couldn't be used to teach anything, because one would already
have to know what the words meant, if he was to learn anything –
and if she knew what they meant, then she wouldn't need anyone to
teach them more.
Armed with such strong
arguments, Pyrrhonians could have just rested on their laurels and
declared all attempts to find knowledge futile. Instead, they went to
quite some length in order to discredit even individual disciplines.
They began with the traditional Greek elementary studies, in order to
show that knowledge could not be found even in such elementary topics.
First of the
elementary studies skeptics rejected was the learning of grammar and
classic literature. Sextus noted that learning grammar was not
altogether useless, because reading and writing were important for
surviving in the real life. It is the supposedly expert part of it,
dealing with intricacies of language that is both useless and
doubtful. An expert of language begins by defining its elements or
individual sounds, but it is problematic to even decide what is an
individual sound. Is a long vowel a separate sound from a short vowel
or just two vowels put together? Is a differently pronounced s
a new sound or a combination of s
with some other sound? Written language is of no help here, because
it is far from being consistent and in some cases it accepts such as
different elements and uses a different letter for them, but in other
cases it uses a combination of several letters.
Combining
sounds into syllables and words is also problematic, because it is
sometimes difficult to distinguish combinations of several syllables
or words from a single syllable or word. Even more inconsistencies
are produced by grammatical genera of words, especially if they are
defined as masculine or feminine. If the experts of language try to
make the linguistic inconsistencies disappear by making all
conjugations and such bound to a rule, the problem is which rule one
should follow in unclear cases. The only sufficient criterion appears
to be the actual language use of different people, but this requires
no expertise and would also mean acceptance of all inconsistencies.
If the experts would want to revert to some original state of
language, they couldn't explain what was better in such archaic forms
– if they were natural, everyone would use them.
The
teachers of grammar also boasted of knowledge of myths and ancient
poets, but this did not impress skeptics. Because myths and poems are
so variable and have different version, there can be no systematic
discipline studying them. Furthermore, trying to find great wisdom in
such works of art is futile, because these works are so inconsistent
in their teachings: should we follow the advice of one character or
of another?
After
grammar, it was rhetoric that faced the skeptic attack. Sextus
ridiculed teachers of fine speeches who rarely made speeches
themselves, and noted that floral expressions of famous orators
rarely received any sympathies from listeners and judges of court
anymore and thus failed to convince or impress, which supposedly was
the major achievement of this art. In addition, he noted that a
community would not benefit from people who could lull others with
pretty words, thus making the status of rhetoric as a useful art
suspect.
Even mathematical arts
weren't left in peace, at least if they passed the limits of what was
required in everyday life. Pyrrhonians criticized the notion of
points as dimensionless entities, out of which were generated
breadthless lines, depthless planes and finally normal bodies. All
that we see, they say, has some dimensions, has breadth and even
depth, so we truly have no reason to suppose the existence of such
non-entities like points, lines and planes. Furthermore, even if such
incorporeal entities existed, it would be mysterious how they could
produce corporeal bodies or even limit them.
Equally suspect in
Pyrrhonians' opinions was the attempt to base arithmetic on the
philosophical notion of One as something that made all things into
unities. Was this One itself a unity? Wouldn't it then make all the
unities into just one entity, thus making it impossible to count
anything. And if it was more like a material that could be divided
and attached to each unity separately, how could we speak of the One
as a unified entity?
It was not practical land
measuring and counting that Pyrrhonians criticized, but theories
supposedly meant as their foundations. Similarly, they were not
antagonistic towards empirical study of stars and their movements,
but towards the attempt to read people's destinies from the position
of the stars at the time of their conception or birth. Pyrrhonians noted
that even if stars do influence human lives, such studies would have
to be of utmost accuracy, because clearly there have been persons
born very close and very near one another and still with quite remote
destinies. Then again, such accuracy is impossible to maintain,
because it is too difficult to determine the exact point at which a
child has been born or conceived.
The final part of
traditional Greek education or music was also argued against by
Pyrrhonians. While music was usually hailed as necessary for
cultivating human character, Pyrrhonians noted that in many cases
music appeared to have quite the opposite effect and that its
apparent good consequences were caused by its capacity to captivate
its listeners. Furthermore, musical education appeared useless to
Pyrrhonians, because even small babies could appreciate good music.
Finally, Pyrrhonians attacked the whole notions of a systematic study
of music, because it consisted of fleeting melodies, which had no
stable structure to be investigated.
Pyrrhonians continued on
to argue against the more refined philosophical disciplines. In the
order of presentation, they mostly followed Stoics, probably because
it was the most famed school at the time. Thus, like Stoics, they
began with logic, but instead of showing how one can find what is
true, they presented arguments against the possibility to find truth.
The other schools had supposed there had to be some group of entities
that were able to decide what is true or not: most of them had
supposed this group contained at least some humans. Now, Pyrrhonians
noted that even recognising someone as a human would require a
commonly accepted definition of humanity, which no one had yet given.
Indeed, because no one had satisfyingly discerned the generally
supposed constituent aspects of humans, that is, material bodies and
mental life, there was no reason to assume a combination of these
aspects was any more understandable.
Even if we could discern
humans from other entities, Pyrrhonians continued, we still could not
accept that humans would be able to know the truth, unless someone
who knew truth confirmed it – thus, another regress was generated.
Further problems were created by the diversity of human opinions –
surely not humans with all their disputes could all be truth
recognisers.
If humans or at least some
of them were still accepted as capable of knowing the truth,
Pyrrhonians could always move on to study the tools by which a human
being knows something. Of these tools, sensations clearly contradict
themselves from time to time, while intellect is somewhat fuzzy
entity, of which nothing much is known for certain – and even we
just accepted it, as it is, different people would appear to have
been lead to different opinions by their intellects. The only option
would then be to let senses and intellect cooperate, but even this
cooperation would be useless, because neither could be used as a
final standard in cases where the senses and intellect disagreed.
Finally, Pyrrhonians
doubted the veracity of the idea that what appeared to us human
beings through either senses or intellect could be used in discerning
truth. Indeed, they said, it is unclear what these appearances are
and how they are produced, so there is nothing to indicate that they
have any connection with truth. Indeed, it appears that appearances
tell more of the internal states of human beings than of any external
objects. We couldn't even say that appearances are similar to the
objects, because we cannot have any direct view of the objects. And
in fact, while appearances contradict one another, there is no
standard for deciding which of them are true.
Pyrrhonians went even
further and even suspected the very existence of truths. Truths
appeared to be something beyond mere perception, because truth is not
a thing that we could literally see. Truth also doesn't appear to be
a linguistic attribute of statements, because statements as temporal
processes come and go and then truth would also vanish after the
statement has been uttered. Then again, if truth was just something
in our thoughts, then no things we perceive would be true, which
would appear strange.
Even more problems arose
from the attempts to know something mediately, through signs or
symbols, just like fire might be recognised through rising smoke.
Sign apparently must then be immediately apparent and clear –
otherwise we couldn't know of it – while that which is known
through a sign must be hidden and unclear – otherwise there
wouldn't be any need to use sign. Problem is, we couldn't know that A
is a sign of B, because we wouldn't be aware of the B at all.
Furthermore, it is problematic whether knowing something as a sign
requires only perception or also thought. If it would require mere
perception, it would be unclear how people conceive different causes
for certain signs, for instance, two doctors who make different
diagnose from same symptoms. Then again, it cannot require thinking,
because even dogs can use signs like smells for information
gathering.
An important subspecies of
sign use that Pyrrhonians also attacked was demonstrations, which
derived formerly unknown truths from known truths. Their main point
was that all apparently valid conclusions were either useless or
inconclusive. Consider, for instance, a proof of the form ”A, if A
then B, thus B”. Here the statement ”if A, then B” is actually
quite problematic. You cannot really know it is true, unless you have
gone through all known cases where the statement A holds. But if you
have done this, then you already know directly that B is also true at
this time, so the whole deduction is pointless. If, on the other
hand, you don't know whether ”if A then B” is true, you cannot
prove B through this argument. Weaker inductive proofs fare even
worse, because one could not generalise from a single observation.
Indeed, Pyrrhonians noted that logicians were not even better in
choosing what arguments to follow than real experts: for instance, a
doctor might know instinctually that certain prescription was not
made right, while logician would have nothing to add to this.
Pyrrhonians also spoke
against the need to define things precisely. Indeed, because
definitions couldn't be made infinitely big, there should be some
ultimate undefined terms, thus showing that skill of defining things
is not always useful. Indeed, many definitions made things even more
obscure by replacing fairly well known terms with further murkiness.
Finally, Pyrrhonians ridiculed the division of classes – if we
cannot even know what these classes are, we cannot really say the
division is complete.
In physical matters
Pyrrhonians could easily refer to the variety of opinions held by
different schools, yet, they took pains in finding arguments against
certain common opinions. Thus, when Stoics tried to argue that
physical matters could be explained by active causes interacting with
passive materials, Pyrrhonians raised doubts against both of them.
The ultimate active cause was often said to be some god or gods, but
Pyrrhonians could also easily bring forward philosophers doubting and
even ridiculing the idea of the existence of gods. For instance, god
would have to be either motionless and even incapable of motion –
rather pathetic god – or else it would love and thus be susceptible
to corruption. This point resembles a basic contradiction in the very
notion of divinity: gods were thought to be good and powerful, but
still they either couldn't manage or wouldn't want to relief the
world of all the suffering. Paradoxically, Pyrrhonians thought that
this lack of definite conclusion was actually best thing that
happened from a religious viewpoint. If no conclusion was certain,
then one should just continue following traditional worship just in
case. Those who wanted to prove the existence of gods, on the other
hand, made religion susceptible to ridicule by blasphemous
counterarguments.
In addition to gods, all
active causes are actually suspect, Pyrrhonians suggested. Firstly,
we couldn't even conceive what causes are, because knowing a cause
would presuppose knowing its effects, which would then presuppose
knowing their cause. Even if one could know what causes are, she
would have to give a cause that would guarantee that there are
causes: this would lead to a never-ending series of causes. Finally,
it is actually in most cases even impossible to distinguish between
the active and the passive components of causal relation. For
instance, when sun, say, dries a piece of clay, sun is not the only
active thing, because the clay itself is acting to allow the drying –
if it would be snow, the result would be quite the contrary, that is,
a wet spot.
Furthermore, Pyrrhonians
thought the very process of causation to be dubious. Presumably
causes either added something to things or took away from them. Now,
such an interaction would in most likelihood occur either between two
bodies or two non-bodily limits of things, like lines, because it
would be difficult to say how e.g. lines could add anything to
bodies. Line then apparently could in a sense take away something
from another line, for instance, when one line cut another in two.
Then again, the very notion of such splitting of lines was very
awkward. If a line could be cut in two, then its parts would have to
have been joined by a point, which the cutting line would then go
through. But where would this middle point then belong? It could not
belong to both parts, or they would still be joined, but if it
belonged to either, the line would not be cut evenly, and if it
belonged to neither, the line would have been cut into three parts.
Similar problems would be faced with combining lines and other limits
of bodies.
The notion of bodies
interacting with one another is equally difficult, Pyrrhonians
continued. Suppose a smaller body is added to another. If the smaller
body truly changed the essence of the larger body, it would make this
other body similar to itself – namely, smaller. Addition would then
actually diminish a thing, which would be absurd. If the smaller
body, on the contrary, would not affect the essence of the other
body, it would not really add anything to the other body, but would
only come in close contact with it.
In addition to causes, the
very things that causes act on are suspect, Pyrrhonians continue.
Most of the philosophical schools assume that there are material
objects or bodies that can be described through geometrical means.
Yet, in order to account for three-dimensional bodies geometrically,
one must regard them as formed from two-dimensional surfaces and
finally from one-dimensional lines – problem is that we can see no
such two- or one-dimensional things flying around anywhere.
Furthermore, it is a mystery how concrete bodies can be thought about
reliably. If we could do it, such thoughts would have to be based on
prior perceptions of bodies, but it seems that we perceive only
fragments of these bodies – we see colours, we smell certain
odours, but our perceptions do not tell us that these colours and
odours go together. Because we cannot directly perceive all such
properties as belonging to one thing, we cannot even think about such
belonging.
This still leaves the
possibility that there could be incorporeal substances that could be
affected by some causes. Problem is that we seem to be unable to
define incorporeal substances without any reference to the corporeal
substances, which were already deemed problematic. In addition,
incorporeal substances cannot be perceived to exist, because they
cannot exert any influence on our sense organs. Furthermore, their
existence cannot even be argued for, because arguments definitely are
not corporeal, so we would have to decide first whether there are
incorporeal things, before we could just assume the existence of
incorporeal substances.
In addition to the general
attack against incorporeal substances, Pyrrhonians also went against
some particular types of such substances, such as place and time. Of
these two, place cannot be material, because then it would repel
bodies, but it cannot also be a void, because then it would vanish,
whenever occupied by a body. Time, on the other hand, consists of a
part that is not yet, a part that is yet to come and of a fleeting
limit between the two – how could it exist? But if place and time
do not exist, how could there be any motion, or indeed, change in
general and thus anything for physics to study? Then again, motion
and change are so natural concepts that defending them requires just
reference to common experiences. Because there are good reasons both
for accepting them and for disregarding them, Pyrrhonians concluded
that we should just refrain to say anything about them.
After physics, Pyrrhonians
set their sights on ethical questions. Here they could easily refer
to the various opinions and customs in different cultures and with
different thinkers, so that any supposed taboo was practiced or at
least allowed by some people: for instance, some of the early Stoics
had seen nothing bad in eating human flesh. Hence, Pyrrhonists
concluded, nothing was naturally good or bad, for otherwise everyone
would think it good or bad.
Furthermore, Pyrrhonists
denied that anyone could really be an expert of how to live. This
couldn't be a natural trick, because then everyone would know it by
instinct and need no philosophers to guide them, but learning how to
live was as impossible as learning in general. Furthermore,
philosophers are often in awe of the idea of a truly good person, but
Pyrrhonians noted that such people are usually like nothing when
compared with even better persons. Finally, supposed experts of good
life lived actually rather poor lives full of all sorts of hardship.
In fact, skeptics appeared
to live much calmer lives than their dogmatic fellows, Pyrrhonians
thought. Latter had all sorts of beliefs about what is good and what
is bad and then spent all their life craving for what is good and
fearing for what is bad, thus making their life full of woe and
misery. Pyrrhonians, on the other hand, had no opinions about the
matter and were thus hurt only by such unavoidable physical feelings
like hunger.
Ei kommentteja:
Lähetä kommentti